The Law of the Conversation of Information and Bernoulli’s Principle of Insufficient Reason

I have just been rereading Bernoulli’s Principle of Insufficient Reason and Conservation of Information in Computer Search by William Dembski and Robert Marks. It is an important paper for the Intelligent Design movement as Dembski and Marks make liberal use of Bernouilli’s Principle of Insufficient Reason (BPoIR) in their papers on the Law of Conservation of Information (LCI) and many ID friendly authors, including Dembski, use it extensively elsewhere. Without BPoIR many of the arguments presented for Intelligent Design would collapse. The point of Dembski and Marks paper is to address some fundamental criticisms of BPoIR. I hope to show that they fail to do this.

For Dembski and Marks BPoIR provides a way of determining the probability of an outcome given no prior knowledge. This is vital to the case for the LCI. The idea of the LCI is that outcomes such as genes or proteins can be seen as successful searches for limited targets in a large search space. The improbability of hitting that target without any prior information (determined using BPoIR) is the total amount of information in that outcome. They then go on to argue that the chances of finding any strategy for increasing the probability of hitting the target (i.e. reducing the information) are always so low that it is not possible to increase the overall probability of hitting the target. The more the strategy increases the probability of success, the lower the probability of finding the strategy. Or as they put it – the information lost through introducing the strategy is always made up for by the information gained in finding the strategy – so that information is conserved – and overall the information based on using BPoIR without prior knowledge is preserved. Their proof of this also relies on BPoIR. So the LCI is deeply dependent on BPoIR.

Dembski and Marks are well aware that BPoIR has been severely criticised by philosophers and statisticians as eminent as J M Keynes. In particular Keynes pointed out that the BPoIR does not give a unique result. A well-known example is applying BPoIR to the specific volume of a given substance. If we know nothing about the specific volume then someone could argue using BPoIR that all specific volumes are equally likely. But equally someone could argue using BPoIR all specific densities are equally likely. However, as one is the reciprocal of the other, these two assumptions are incompatible. This is an example based on continuous measurements and Dembski and Marks refer to it in the paper. However, having referred to it, they do not address it. Instead they concentrate on the examples of discrete measurements where they offer a sort of response to Keynes’ objections. What they attempt to prove is rather limited point about discrete cases such as a pack of cards or protein of a given length. It is hard to write their claim concisely – but I will give it a try.

Imagine you have a search space such as a normal pack of cards and a target such as finding a card which is a spade. Then it is possible to argue by BpoIR that, because all cards are equal, the probability of finding the target with one draw is 0.25. Dembski and Marks attempt to prove that in cases like this that if you decide to do a “some to many” mapping for this search space into another space then you have only a 50% chance of creating a new search space where BPoIR gives a higher probability of finding a spade. A “some to many” mapping means some different way of viewing the pack of cards so that it is not necessary that all of them are considered and some of them may be considered more often than others. For example, you might take a handful out of the pack at random and then duplicate some of that handful a few times – and then select from what you have created.

What is the significance of this? It is not totally clear. I think their point is that a “some to many mapping” is equivalent to changing the probability of the individual items in the search space from the BPoIR assumption of every outcome being equal, to any other distribution of probabilities e.g. making one amino acid more probable than another when building a protein. So they have attempted to prove that if instead of assuming all amino acids are equal you take another probability distribution at random, you have a 50% or less chance of happening on a probability distribution which will improve your chance of meeting the target.

There are two problems with this.

1) It does not address Keynes’ objection to BPoIR

2) The proof itself depends on an unjustified use of BPoIR.

But before that it is worth commenting on the concept of no prior knowledge.

The Concept of No Prior Knowledge

Dembski and Marks’ case is that BPoIR gives the probability of an outcome when we have no prior knowledge. They stress that this means no prior knowledge of any kind and that it is “easy to take for granted things we have no right to take for granted” (They compare it to the physics concept of nothing that preceded the big bang). However, there are deep problems associated with this concept. The act of defining a search space and a target implies prior knowledge. Consider finding a spade in pack of cards. To apply BPoIR at minimum you need to know that a card can be one of four suits, that 25% of the cards have a suit of spades, and that the suit does not affect the chances of that card being selected. The last point is particularly relevant. BPoIR justifies us in claiming that the probability of two or more events are the same. But the events must differ in some respects (even if it is only a difference in when or where they happen) or they would be the same event. To apply BPoIR we have to know (or assume) that these differences are not relevant to the probability of the events happening. We must somehow judge that the suit of the card, the head or tails symbols on the coin, or the choice of DNA base pair is irrelevant to that the chances of that card, coin toss or base pair being selected. This is prior knowledge.

In addition, as Keynes pointed out, the more we try to dispense with assumptions and knowledge about an event then the more difficult it becomes to decide how to apply BPoIR. Another of Keynes examples is a bag of 100 black and white balls in an unknown ratio of black to white. Do we assume that all ratios of black to white are equally likely or do we assume that each individual ball is equally likely to be black or white? Either assumption is equally justified by BPoIR but they are incompatible. One results in a uniform probability distribution for the number of white balls from zero to 100; the other results in a binomial distribution which greatly favours roughly equal numbers of black and while balls. To choose the correct assumptions we would have to know more, for example the process by which the bag was filled.

Now I will turn to the problems with the proof in Dembski and Marks’ paper.

The Proof does not Address Keynes’ objection to BPoIR

Even if the proof were valid (I believe I show below that it is not) then it does nothing to show that the assumption of BPoIR is correct. All it shows is that if you make an assumption other than what Dembski and Marks believe follows from BPoIR then you have 50% or less chance of improving your chances of finding target. The fact remains that there are many other assumptions you could make and some of them greatly increase your chances of finding the target. There is nothing in the proof that in anyway justifies assuming BPoIR or giving it any kind of privileged position.

But the problem is even deeper. Keynes’ point was not that there are alternatives to using BPoIR – that’s obvious. His point was that there are different incompatible ways of applying BPoIR. For example, just as with the example of black and white balls above, we might use BPoIR to deduce that all ratios of base pairs in a string of DNA are equally likely. Dembski and Marks do not address this at all. They point out the trap of taking things for granted but fall foul of it themselves.

The Proof Relies on an Unjustified Use of BPoIR

The proof is found in appendix A of the paper and this is the vital line:

image

This is the probability that a new search space created from an old one will include k members which were part of the target in the original search space. The equation holds true if the new search space is created by selecting elements from old search space at random; for example, by picking a random number of cards at random from a pack. It uses BPoIR to justify the assumption that each unique way of picking cards is equally likely. This can be made clearer with an example.

Suppose the original search space comprises just the four DNA bases, one of which is the target. Call them x, y, z and t. Using BPoIR, Dembski and Marks would argue that all of them are equally likely and therefore the probability of finding t with a single search is 0.25. They then consider all the possible ways you might take a subset of that search space. This comprises:

Subsets with

no items

just one item: x,y,z and t

with two items: xy, xz, yz, tx, ty, tz

with three items: xyz, xyt, xzt, yzt

with four items: xyzt

A total of 16 subsets.

Their point is that if you assume each of these subsets if equally likely (so the probability of one of them being selected is 1/16) then 50% of them have a probability of finding t which is greater than or equal to probability in the original search space (i.e. 0.25). To be specific new search spaces where probability of finding t is greater than 0.25 are t, tx, ty, tz, xyt, xzt, yzt and xyzt. That is 8 out of 16 which is 50%.

But what is the justification for assuming each of these subsets are equally likely? Well it requires using BPoIR which the proof is meant to defend. And even if you grant the use of BPoIR Keynes’ concerns apply. There is more than one way to apply BPoIR and not all of them support Dembski and Marks’ proof. Suppose for example the subset was created by the following procedure:

· Start with one member selected at random as the subset

· Toss a dice,

o If it is two or less then stop and use current set as subset

o If it is a higher than two then add another member selected at random to the subset

· Continue tossing until dice throw is two or less or all four members in are in subset

This gives a completely different probability distribution.

The probability of:

single item subset (x,y,z, or t) = 0.33/4 = 0.083

double item subset (xy, xz, yz, tx, ty, or tz) = 0.66*0.33/6 = 0.037

triple item subset (xyz, xyt, xzt, or yzt) = 0.66*0.33*0.33/4 = 0.037

four item subset (xyzt) = 0.296

So the combined probability of the subsets where probability of selecting t is ≥ 0.25 (t, tx, ty, tz, xyt, xzt, yzt, xyzt) = 0.083+3*(0.037)+3*(0.037)+0.296 = 0.60 (to 2 dec places) which is bigger than 0.5 as calculated using Dembski and Marks assumptions. In fact using this method, the probability of getting a subset where the probability of selecting t ≥ 0.25 can be made as close to 1 as desired by increasing the probability of adding a member. All of these methods treat all four members of the set equally and are equally justified under BpoIR as Dembski and Marks assumption.

Conclusion

Dembski and Marks paper places great stress on BPoIR being the way to calculate probabilities when there is no prior knowledge. But their proof itself includes prior knowledge. It is doubtful whether it makes sense to eliminate all prior knowledge, but if you attempt to eliminate as much prior knowledge as possible, as Keynes does, then BPoIR proves to be an illusion. It does not give a unique result and some of the results are incompatible with their proof.

21 thoughts on “The Law of the Conversation of Information and Bernoulli’s Principle of Insufficient Reason”

  1. Pingback: The Skeptical Zone
  2. Canola oil is nutritious and penetrating for all
    skin types. Do this with care, as the juice will stain everything it touches a nice, rich brown.

    But this is not a hopeless condition because you can do something to diminish the
    appearance of eyebags.

  3. Perhaps you recall chamomile from the times you were sick and your parent, friend,
    or partner, gave you a hot cup of this therapeutic drink to ease your suffering stomach.
    The lack of natural oils and moisture in the hair is the most important factor for
    the increasing hair problems of today. I was so upset because
    I was living at the beach and having a tan was so important to
    me.

  4. I suck in compliments like a sponge and absorb as much pleasure as possible from each and every one.
    Of all the healthy oils, hemp oil delivers the most of essential fatty acids, making it excellent for those
    suffering from diabetes and high cholesterol.
    Blanch, but turn off heat the moment the water
    comes to a boil.

  5. We are a group of volunteers and starting a new scheme
    in our community. Your website offered us with valuable info to
    work on. You have done a formidable job and our entire community
    will be grateful to you.

  6. Since the production of this oil contributed
    mostly to the medical therapy, the creation of the oil contributed much to the females of the native Berber group in Morocco to have a steady source of income and good working conditions and was able to build up their literacy and various education
    courses. Since this hair product can penetrate deep, it helps reverses the damage caused by chemicals, leaving
    your hair safe and protected despite it being color treated.
    Prostaglandin is a natural anti-inflammatory and acts as a controlling factor
    in overall cell growth and development.

  7. I’m not sure where you’re getting your info, but good topic.

    I needs to spend some time learning much more or understanding more.
    Thanks for excellent information I was looking for this information for
    my mission.

  8. Hmm is anyone else experiencing problems with the images on this blog loading?
    I’m trying to find out if its a problem on my end or if it’s the
    blog. Any feedback would be greatly appreciated.
    Danilo

  9. Incredible, . human resources staffing agencyoutstanding web site page layout! Just how prolonged were you blogs for? you’ve made writing a blog look simple. The entire peek of this site is exceptional, in addition to the written content!

  10. Pingback: Proof of Concept
  11. Pingback: jacks-handys.de

Leave a comment